100 Philosophie und Psychologie
Refine
Year of publication
Document Type
- Article (636)
- Part of a Book (103)
- Review (97)
- Book (78)
- Doctoral Thesis (65)
- Contribution to a Periodical (40)
- Part of Periodical (34)
- Working Paper (22)
- Report (21)
- magisterthesis (11)
Language
- German (585)
- Portuguese (217)
- English (161)
- Spanish (81)
- Italian (28)
- French (13)
- Ukrainian (9)
- Slovak (5)
- Catalan (4)
- Multiple languages (4)
Keywords
- Adorno (55)
- Philosophie (50)
- Critical Theory (32)
- Reconhecimento (27)
- Frankfurt School (26)
- Axel Honneth (25)
- Recognition (25)
- Ästhetik (25)
- Erkenntnistheorie (20)
- Teoria Crítica (18)
Institute
- Philosophie (557)
- Gesellschaftswissenschaften (392)
- Institut für Sozialforschung (IFS) (351)
- Präsidium (53)
- Exzellenzcluster Die Herausbildung normativer Ordnungen (38)
- Philosophie und Geschichtswissenschaften (24)
- Universitätsbibliothek (20)
- Neuere Philologien (16)
- Extern (15)
- Geschichtswissenschaften (14)
This article shows that the German philosopher Hermann Schmitz’s new phenomenology can make a valuable contribution to human–animal studies. The three concepts suitable for this purpose are, first, Schmitz’s concept of embodied communication, which can be applied to trans-species encounters; second, his understanding of atmospheres, which are always co-communicated in trans-species encounters; and, third, his conception of situation, which can help with analyzing the relationship of society to animals. My contribution applies these three basic elements of new phenomenology—embodied communication, atmosphere, and situation—to the analysis of the encounters between humans and horses. This paper demonstrates that embodied communication in particular is not only a worthwhile object of research but can also serve as a mode of producing scientific insight.
This thesis investigates a selection of nineteenth-century handcrafted Indian souvenir objects housed in the Ethnological Collection of Lübeck, and connects them to the context of British colonialism in the Indian subcontinent, and to the broader global networks of European tourism within which they were produced and circulated. Focusing on those objects especially neglected in museum research as tourist memorabilia, on account of their serialised production or European stylistic influence, this thesis examines the colonial structures that promoted their production and enabled their mobility between India, Germany, and Britain. Taking a multi-disciplinary approach to object research, it moves beyond the biographies of the collectors, and questions how the production of such objects for European tourists offers us access to a further dimension of colonial intervention in India.
Throughout the nineteenth century, Indian handicrafts were increasingly woven into the global and political power relations playing out on the colonial stage, in a categorically asymmetrical way. This thesis addresses four specific issues: first, it argues that a history of Indian handicrafts was reframed by colonialism to fit its discourse, often ignoring intermingling artistic influences and exchanges between and across pre-colonial kingdoms, in the quest to define and fix an ‘India’, and a unified idea of Indian art. Second, it argues that handicrafts played a role in the systems of colonial knowledge production in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, that sought to legitimise colonial rule. Third, it demonstrates how the representation of crafts at international exhibitions and world fairs allowed the British to construct a curated vision of India for their European audience. And fourth, it argues that orientalist scholarship used print media to enact particular forms of visual encoding and textual discourse in order to reconfigure handicrafts to maintain India’s alterity.
These imaginations of India generated a popular, exoticised appreciation for Indian material in the West. My thesis argues that this increased demand for objects was answered by their serialised production, and adherence to certain forms and styles to ensure their commercial viability. By connecting the objects to the contexts of their production, my original contribution to knowledge is the development of a critical framework by which to review hybrid, souvenir, and tourist art from the Indian subcontinent. The findings of this thesis contribute to the fields of Indian handicraft history, South Asian art-history, postcolonial museum anthropology, and research practices for material culture from colonial tourism contexts.
This paper challenges the role individual autonomy has played in debates on moral neuroenhancement (MN). It shows how John Hyman's analysis of agency as consisting of functionally integrated dimensions allows us to reassess the impact of MN on practical agency. I discuss how MN affects what Hyman terms the four dimensions of agency: psychological, ethical, intellectual, and physical. Once we separate the different dimensions of agency, it becomes clear that many authors in the debate conflate the different dimensions in the concept they call ‘autonomous agents’. They contend that, for example, reason-giving and previous autonomous acts are relevant to agency as such, when in fact they capture only one aspect of functionally integrated agency. This paper reconsiders MN in light of the functional integration of reason and emotions in practical agency. To illustrate the impact of MN on different aspects of agency, I consider examples from legal practice, which show that autonomy cannot be our sole focus when evaluating the moral implications of MN.
This paper offers a partial defence of the Epicurean claim that death is not bad for the one who dies. Unlike Epicurus and his present-day advocates, this defence relies not on a hedonistic or empiricist conception of value but on the concept of ‘existential’ value. Existential value is agent-relative value for which it is constitutive that it can be truly self-ascribed in the first person and present tense. From this definition, it follows that death (post-mortem non-existence), while perhaps bad in some respects, cannot be an existential harm for the one who dies. This paper argues that existential goods are central to any explanation of why life appears good to us from a self-interested perspective, which means that death is not bad in the very respect in which life is most saliently good (from that perspective). A corresponding error theory shows why this truth is easily overlooked and explains why we tend to think that death is significantly worse than it really is.
How does causation in the physical world relate to implication in logic? This article presents implication as fundamentally a relation of inclusion between propositions. Given this, it is argued that an event cannot “causally imply” another, also given the laws of nature. Then, by applying the notion of inclusion to physical objects, a relation “within the possibilities of” is developed, which generates a partial order on sets of entities and is independent of time. Based on this, it is shown that changes of physical objects in time (at any rate, a great many of them) imply, and thus counterfactually depend on, what we call “causes” – an asymmetric dependence which is robust despite the perspectival nature of the concept of “cause”.
he present paper argues that, despite appearance to the contrary, Kierkegaard’s writings offer promising argumentational resources for addressing the problem of evil. According to Kierkegaard, however, in order to make use of these resources at all, one must necessarily be willing to shift the battleground, so to speak: from a third- to a genuine first-person perspective, namely the perspective of what Climacus dubs Religiousness A. All (yet also only) those who seek deliberate self-annihilation before God—a God in relation to whom they perceive themselves always in the wrong—shall discover the ideal that an unwavering and in fact unconditional thankfulness (namely, for being forgiven) is to be considered the only appropriate attitude towards God and as such both necessary and sufficient for coming to terms with evil and suffering, at least in the life of someone making that discovery. I will argue that Kierkegaard’s (non-)pseudonymous writings provide reasons, at times unwittingly, for adopting the perspective of Religiousness A; however, I will also and ultimately argue that the principle of infinite thankfulness as a corollary of that perspective flounders when it comes to making sense of (the eschatological implications of) the suffering of others.
Cryopreservation practices have become increasingly important within contemporary life sciences in recent decades, opening up the perspective of modifying and modulating temporal pathways and developmental cycles. Exploring the concept of “suspended life,” this article first focuses on temporal liminality as cryopreservation practices operate by extending the present. I rely on Niklas Luhmann’s account of time, which advances the idea of an enduring present bound to the principle of reversibility. The second part of this article engages with the emergence of cryobanks. Drawing on Martin Heidegger’s concept of the “standing-reserve” (Bestand), I conceive of cryobanks as storing facilities that ensure the disposition of organic material. The third section discusses the advent of a “politics of suspension” based on the proliferation of cryogenic life in contemporary societies, which is defined by reversibility and disposition. The conclusion sums up the main argument and briefly points to the social and political repercussions of this mode of governing the future by prolonging the present.
One of the central themes of this essay is the contrast between two notions of conceivability, which, as a first approximation, may be circumscribed in terms of the distinction between what is rationally imaginable (imaginative conceivability), as opposed to what is rationally believable (doxastic conceivability, i.e. the dual of indubitability). In recent years, the philosophy of conceivability has been dominated by the question whether conceivability, in some suitable sense, entails possibility. This essay shifts focus toward the question whether imaginative conceivability entails doxastic conceivability; and in the last two chapters addresses the question whether possibility entails conceivability, in either of the two above senses. Much of the discussion will focus on the characteristic truths of classical first-order logic with identity, and in particular on singular existential sentences, i.e. sentences stating the existence of some respective individual. Once suitably regimented, sentences of this kind figure as theorems in classical first-order logic. According to the received view, this circumstance is a mere artifact resulting from simplifying stipulations in the formal semantics of first-order logic, and should not be taken as an indication that singular existential sentences are logically true in any substantial respect. Although this caveat is legitimate as far as it goes, it will be suggested that in one important but unduly neglected sense of logical truth, true singular existential sentences are not just true, but indeed logically true. In particular, it will be argued that the proposition expressed by the negation of a singular existential sentence fails to be doxastically conceivable.
The claim is discussed in semantic, pragmatic, epistemological and logical respect and defended against foreseeable objections extracted from a variety of philosophical views ranging from skepticism to disquotationalism, temporalism, descriptivism, the causal theory of reference, as well as coarse- and fine-grained conceptions of propositional content. Also discussed are the claim’s ramifications for traditional notions of analyticity and apriority. Two equally legitimate notions of analyticity will be distinguished, one strictly stronger than the other, and true singular existential sentences will be found to be weakly if not strongly analytic. As regards apriority, it is argued that if true singular existentials are not a priori, then, since they are indubitable, some propositions are indubitable even if not a priori. Conversely, if all indubitable propositions are a priori, then, since true singular existentials are indubitable, they are a priori, and presumably many of them will have to be countenanced as novel examples of the Kripkean category of the contingent a priori. Either consequence would be of significance, the former to epistemology in general, the latter to the epistemology of existence in particular.
Aus dem Gutachten: In der Arbeit wird "die politische Theorie von Cornelius Castoriadis „als ein genuin gesellschaftskritisches und politikkritisches Unterfangen“ der „Neuformulierung revolutionärer Theorie“ zu rekonstruieren. Er folgt damit dem Anliegen, „die Konsistenz seines Werks“ und „den inneren Zusammenhang seiner Schriften“ bzw. „seiner Kritik“ über die verschiedenen Phasen von Castoriadis‘ Schaffen hinweg aufzuzeigen. Im Zuge dessen lässt [der Autor] die Theorie Castoriadis‘ plastisch werden als kritische Theorie „einer verdinglichten Gesellschaft, die sich dem Bewusstsein ihrer selbst (bisher) als pro-duzierte oder geschöpfte entzogen hat“ – und für deren Analyse Autonomie nicht bloßes normatives Postulat, sondern „logisches Prinzip der Kritik“ ist. Dabei geht es Castoriadis dem Verfasser zufolge letztlich darum, „die radikale Selbstsetzung des Subjekts vor seiner Vereinnahmung durch ein abgeschlossenes Allgemeines zu retten, bei gleichzeitiger Rettung eines Begriffs von Allgemeinheit […] vor schlechter Beliebigkeit“."
Eintrachtfan und Philosoph
(2024)